Tuesday, September 15, 2020

Coronavirus, Civil Liberties, and the Courts: The Case Against “Suspending” Judicial Review - Harvard Law Review

JudgeJMHarlan.jpg
John Marshall Harlan, Associate Justice
1877-1911
In the truly landmark case of Jacobson v. Massachusetts 197 U.S. 11 (1905) Justice John Marshall Harlan, reviewing a $5 fine for failure to consent to vaccination against smallpox, explained for the Supreme Court that it is within the police power of a State to enact a compulsory vaccination law, and it is for the legislature, and not for the courts, to determine in the first instance whether vaccination is or is not the best mode for the prevention of smallpox and the protection of the public health.
That plain statement of judicial deference to elected officials was followed by another that has become the part best remembered, and cited most often in this the moment of the corona virus pandemic:

[W]hen faced with a society-threatening epidemic, a state may implement emergency measures that curtail constitutional rights so long as the measures have at least some “real or substantial relation” to the public health crisis and are not “beyond all question, a plain, palpable invasion of rights secured by the fundamental law.

Texas law professors Lindsay Wiley and Stephen Vladeck in a new essay warn against the common view that 
invocation of "emergency" means the "suspension" of judicial review.  
Wiley and Vladeck argue that it means neither: that ordinary judicial review standards are 
adequate - that attention to the facts and an independent eye are the norm that judges should 
be following lest this "emergency" - like others, morph into the new normal, with rights 
casually restricted and courts keeping hands off. - GWC 
Coronavirus, Civil Liberties, and the Courts: The Case Against “Suspending” Judicial Review - Harvard Law Review
by   & 

In this Essay, we argue that the suspension approach to judicial review is wrong — not just as applied to governmental actions taken in response to novel coronavirus, but in general. As we explain, the current crisis helps to underscore at least three independent objections to the “suspension” model some courts have derived from decisions like Jacobson and Avino. These critiques likewise apply to instances in which courts purport to adopt the appropriate standard of review but do not actually apply it with appropriate rigor.26×26. See, e.g., Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 214, 216–18 (1944) (holding that internment of Japanese Americans passed “the most rigid scrutiny,” id. at 216, because of the compelling interests presented by national security concerns). Korematsu has been roundly rejected as part of the constitutional anticanon. Jamal Greene, The Anticanon, 125 HARV. L. REV. 379, 380, 387–90 (2011). In the absence of such a clear repudiation, soft applications of constitutional standards of review in times of crisis may create dangerous precedent for future applications of those standards once the crisis has passed. Justice Jackson articulated this concern in his Korematsu dissent: “[O]nce a judicial opinion . . . rationalizes the Constitution to show that the Constitution sanctions such an order, the Court for all time has validated the principle of racial discrimination.” 323 U.S. at 246 (Jackson, J., dissenting).
First, the suspension principle is inextricably linked with the idea that a crisis is of finite — and brief — duration. To that end, the principle is ill-suited for long-term and open-ended emergencies like the one in which we currently find ourselves.
Second, and relatedly, the suspension model is based upon the oft-unsubstantiated assertion that “ordinary” judicial review will be too harsh on government actions in a crisis — and could therefore undermine the efficacy of the government’s response. In contrast, as some of the coronavirus cases have already demonstrated, most of these measures would have met with the same fate under “ordinary” scrutiny, too.27×27. Cf., e.g., Legacy Church, Inc. v. Kunkel, No. CIV 20-0327, 2020 WL 1905586, at *36 n.12 (D.N.M. Apr. 17, 2020) (rejecting First Amendment challenges by a church to an order prohibiting gatherings without social distancing on the alternative ground that the order survives strict scrutiny). The principles of proportionality and balancing driving most modern constitutional standards permit greater incursions into civil liberties in times of greater communal need. That is the essence of the “liberty regulated by law” described by the Court in Jacobson.28×28. Jacobson, 197 U.S. at 27 (quoting Crowley v. Christensen, 137 U.S. 86, 90 (1890)).
Finally, the most critical failure of the suspension model is that it does not account for the importance of an independent judiciary in a crisis — “as perhaps the only institution that is in any structural position to push back against potential overreaching by the local, state, or federal political branches.”29×29. Wiley & Vladeck, supra note 3. Indeed, as Professor Ilya Somin has put it, “imposing normal judicial review on emergency measures can help reduce the risk that the emergency will be used as a pretext to undermine constitutional rights and weaken constraints on government power even in ways that are not really necessary to address the crisis.”30×30. Ilya Somin, The Case for “Regular” Judicial Review of Coronavirus Emergency PoliciesVOLOKH CONSPIRACY (Apr. 15, 2020, 4:16 PM), https://reason.com/2020/04/15/the-case-for-normal-judicial-review-of-coronavirus-emergency-policies [https://perma.cc/W82D-NKRN]. Otherwise, we risk ending up with decisions like Korematsu v. United States31×31. 323 U.S. 214. — in which courts sustain gross violations of civil rights because they are either unwilling or unable to meaningfully look behind the government’s purported claims of exigency...

No comments:

Post a Comment