Last week at the Law & Liberty blog, Professor John McGinnis, a self-proclaimed originalist, was quite giddy about the Court's Second Amendment opinion in New York Pistol & Rifle Association v. Bruen striking down a New York law requiring a special permit to conceal carry a handgun. His essay, titled "Bruen's Originalism," takes away three main points from the case:
Leaving aside the obvious point that the Court's
historical analysis was an after-the-fact cobbled-together rationale for a
result reached on other grounds, I want to focus this post on McGinnis' first
point about "expected applications.” If McGinnis is descriptively
right, his analysis goes a long way to showing why true originalism is either
intolerable or impossible.
McGinnis concedes that there is an
intramural debate among academic originalists concerning "expected
applications." He says the following:
One of the
controversial issues in originalist theory is the use of “expected
applications.” Expected applications are instances of how those around the time
of enactment thought the provisions or provisions with similar language would
be applied. Some originalists, like Jack Balkin, reject expected applications
even as evidence of what the Constitution means, preferring to interpret the
text as enacted, unmediated by the applications surrounding the era of
enactment. In contrast, Mike Rappaport and I believe that the expected
applications are often good evidence—sometimes the best evidence—of what the
text actually meant....Thomas clearly embraces expected applications.
I don't think this
really captures Balkin's position but it does accurately state the opposition
to strong reliance on expected applications by most New Originalists, including
Professor Larry Solum. For example, in trying to justify why the 14th Amendment
protects against gender discrimination today, given that we know that was not
the original expectations of those who wrote and ratified the Amendment, Solum
has said the following:
[I]n Bradwell v. Illinois, the Supreme Court
upheld Myra Bradwell’s exclusion from the Illinois bar on the basis of gender.
. . . Bradwell could have been understood as consistent with
the [Privileges or Immunities Clause] by Justices who believed that women were
intellectually incapable of functioning as competent lawyers. The opposite
result would be required [today] given true beliefs about women’s intellectual
capacities. Fixed original public meaning can give rise to different
outcomes given changing beliefs about facts. The Constraint Principle
does not require constitutional actors to adhere to false factual beliefs held
by the drafters, Framers, ratifiers, or the public.
I doubt McGinnis would agree that known expected
applications of imprecise language can be waved away by later judges just
because of "changing beliefs about facts." That is why, I
think, McGinnis believes there is disagreement among originalists about how
binding expected applications actually are on judges. Solum's approach, as I've
written many times before, is indistinguishable from living or common law
constitutionalism (see below). I don't think McGinnis is a living
constitutionalist.
Five other Justices joined Thomas' opinion. Let's assume
McGinnis is right and the expected applications of those who ratified and voted
for constitutional text provide very strong evidence of what the words
originally meant, and judges should follow that evidence. What would that
approach, faithfully applied, mean for constitutional law. Hold on to your
seats.
No comments:
Post a Comment